epistemological shift pros and cons
caesars 5x tier credits 2021In fact, he claims, the two come apart in both directions: yielding knowledge without strong cognitive achievement andas in the case of understanding that lacks corresponding knowledgestrong cognitive achievement without knowledge. Kvanvig stipulates that there are no falsehoods in the relevant class of beliefs that this individual has acquired from the book, and also that she can correctly answer all relevant questions whilst confidently believing that she is expressing the truth. Often-cited discussion of the fake barn counterexample to traditional accounts of knowledge that focus on justified true belief. Outlines a view on which understanding something requires making reasonable sense of it. This is because Stella lacks beliefs on the matter, even though the students can gain understanding from her. Baker, L. R. Third Person Understanding in A. Sanford (ed. This leaves us, however, with an interesting question about the point at which there is no understanding at all, rather than merely weaker or poorer understanding. So, on Grimms (2011) view, grasping the relationships between the relevant parts of the subject matter amounts to possessing the ability to work out how changing parts of that system would or would not impact on the overall system. Pritchard, D. Epistemic Luck. Elgin, C. Exemplification, Idealization, and Understanding in M. Surez (ed. The underlying idea in play here is that, in short, thinking about how things would be if it were true is an efficacious way to get to further truths; an insight has attracted endorsement in the philosophy of science (for example, Batterman 2009). However, Kelp admits that he wonders how his account will make sense of the link between understanding and explanation, and one might also wonder whether it is too strict to say that understanding requires knowledge as opposed to justified belief or justified true belief. Trout, J.D. Criticizes Grimms view of understanding as knowledge of causes. For example, we might require that the agent make sense of X in a way that is reasonablefew would think that the psychic above is reasonable, though it is beyond the scope of the current discussion to stray into exploring accounts of reasonableness. Utilize at least 2 credible sources to support your position presented in the paper. In particular, as Pritchard suggests, we might want to consider that agents working with the ideal gas law or other idealizations do not necessarily have false beliefs as a result, even if the content of the proposition expressed by the law is not strictly true. Another seemingly promising lineone that engages with the relation question discussed aboveviews grasping as intimately connected with a certain set of abilities. Pritchard, D. Knowledge and Understanding in A. Fairweather (ed. Riggs, W. Why Epistemologists Are So Down on Their Luck. Synthese 158 (3) (2007): 329-344. Grimm (2012) has wondered whether this view might get things explanatorily backwards. Pritchard, D. Knowledge, Understanding and Epistemic Value In A. OHear (ed. If a grasping condition is necessary for understanding, does one satisfy this condition only when one exercises a grasping ability to reflect how things are in the world? reptarium brian barczyk; new milford high school principal; salisbury university apparel store If the latterthat is, if we are to understand grasping literally, then, also unfortunately, we are rarely given concrete details of its nature. Defends views that hold explanation as indispensable for account of understanding and discusses what a non-factive account of grasping would look like. And, thirdly, two questions about what is involved in grasping can easily be run together, but should be kept separate. Finally, Section 6 proposes various potential avenues for future research, with an eye towards anticipating how considerations relating to understanding might shed light on a range of live debates elsewhere in epistemology and in philosophy more generally. In other words, even though there is no such gas as that referred to in the law, accepting the law need not involve believing the law to be true and thus believing there to be some gas with properties that it lacks. The Value of Understanding In D. Pritchard, A. Haddock and A. Millar (eds. Establishes a pro position, supporting that the shift in how people take in knowledge is good. Pros and Cons of Epistemological Shift Epistemology refers to a dynamic concept that shows how humans understand knowledge, which entails how it is received, classified, justified, and transmitted in distinctive ways and at different periods in history. . This is the idea that one has shifted, or changed, the way he or she takes in knowledge. Builds an account of understanding according to which understanding a subject matter involves possessing a representation that could be manipulated in a useful way. Contains Kims classic discussion of species of dependence (for example, mereological dependence). Khalifa, K. Is Understanding Explanatory or Objectual? Synthese 190(6) (2013a): 1153-1171. This skeptical argument is worth engaging with, presumably with the goal of showing that understanding does not turn out to be internally indistinguishable from mere intelligibility. Putting this all together, a scientist who embraces the ideal gas law, as an idealization, would not necessarily have any relevant false beliefs. Achievements, unlike mere successes, are regarded as valuable for their own sake, mainly because of the way in which these special sorts of successes come to be. In his article "A Seismic Shift in Epistemology" (2008), Chris Dede draws a distinction between classical perceptions of knowledge and the approach to knowledge underpinning Web 2.0 activity. Since it is central to her take on human evolution, factivists like Kvanvig must conclude that her take on human evolution does not qualify as understanding. Some (for example, Gordon 2012) suggest that attributions of propositional understanding typically involve attributes of propositional knowledge or a more comprehensive type of understandingunderstanding-why, or objectual understanding (these types are examined more closely below). This view, embraced by DePaul and Grimm (2009), implies that to the extent that understanding and knowledge come apart, it is not with respect to a difference in susceptibility to being undermined by epistemic luck. Hazlett, A. An earlier paper defending the intellectualist view of know-how. epistemological shift pros and cons. It is also becoming an increasingly popular position to hold that understanding is more epistemically valuable than knowledge (see Kvanvig 2003; Pritchard 2010). epistemological shift pros and cons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011. Section 4 examines the relationship between understanding and types of epistemic luck that are typically thought to undermine knowledge. What is it to have this ability to modify some mental representation? Outlines and evaluates the anti-intellectualist and intellectualist views of know-how. She claims, it may be possible to know without knowing one knows, but it is impossible to understand without understanding one understands (2001: 246) and suggests that this property of understanding might insulate it from skepticism. Her line is that understanding-why involves (i) knowing what something is, and (ii) making reasonable sense of it. However, it is less clear at least initially that retreating from causal dependence to more general dependence will be of use in the kinds of objectual understanding cases noted above. In recent years epistemology has experienced gradual changes that are critical in human life. The Varieties of Cognitive Success 1.1 What Kinds of Things Enjoy Cognitive Success? ), Intellectual Virtue: Perspectives from Ethics and Epistemology. Contains Lackeys counterexamples to the knowledge transmission principles. This is a change from the past. An overview of coherentism that can be useful when considering how theories of coherence might be used to flesh out the grasping condition on understanding. ), Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives. Hempel, C. Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science. Consider the view that the kinds of epistemic luck that suffice to undermine knowledge do not also undermine understanding. With each step in the sequence, we understand the motion of the planets better than we did before. Riaz, A. manage list views salesforce. In short: understanding is causal propositional knowledge. If so, why, and if not why not? Dordrecht: Reidel, 1979. The childs opinion displays some grasp of evolution. The surgeons successful bypass is valued differently when one is made aware that it was by luck that he picked an appropriate blood vessel for the bypass. Kelp, C. Understanding Phenomena. Synthese (2015). Since Kvanvig claims that the coherence-making relationships that are traditionally construed as necessary for justification on a coherentist picture are the very relations that one grasps (for example, the objects of grasping) when one understands, the justification literature may be a promising place to begin. Grimm (2006) and Pritchard (2010) counter that many of the most desirable instances of potential understanding, such as when we understand another persons psychology or understand how the world works, are not transparent. Epistemology is often defined as the theory of knowledge, and talk of propositional knowledge (that is, S knows that p) has dominated the bulk of modern literature in epistemology. Therefore, the need to adopt a weak factivity constraint on objectual understandingat least on the basis of cases that feature idealizationslooks at least initially to be unmotivated in the absence of a more sophisticated view about the relationship between factivity, belief and acceptance (however, see Elgin 2004). The ambiguity between assenting to a necessary proposition and the grasping or seeing of certain properties and their necessary relatedness mirrors the ambiguity between assenting to a casual proposition and grasping or seeing of the terms of the causal relata: their modal relatedness. More generally, as this line of criticism goes, sometimes we simply mistake mere (non-factive) intelligibility for understanding. Zagzebski notes that this easily leads to a vicious circle because neglect leads to fragmentation of meaning, which seems to justify further neglect and further fragmentation until eventually a concept can disappear entirely.. The following sections consider why understanding might have such additional value. Kvanvig does not spell out what grasping might involve, in the sense now under consideration, in his discussion of coherence, and the other remarks we considered above. (2007: 37), COPERNICUS: A central tenet of Copernicuss theory is the contention that the Earth travels around the sun in a circular orbit. Discusses the connection between curiosity and true belief. 0. Strevens, M. No Understanding Without Explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 44 (2013): 510-515. For example: Although a moderate view of understandings factivity may look promising in comparison with competitor accounts, many important details remain left to be spelled out. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999. Firstly, achievement is often defined as success that is because of ability (see, for example, Greco 2007), where the most sensible interpretation of this claim is to see the because as signifying a casual-explanatory relationshipthis is, at least, the dominant view. Grimm anticipates this point and expresses a willingness to embrace a looser conception of dependence than causal dependence, one that includes (following Kim 1994) species of dependence such as mereological dependences (that is, dependence of a whole on its parts), evaluative dependences (that is, dependence of evaluative on non-evaluative), and so on. Although a large number of epistemologists hold that understanding is not a species of knowledge (e.g. Pritchard maintains that it is intuitive that in the case just described understanding is attainedyou have consulted a genuine fire officer and have received all the true beliefs required for understanding why your house burned down, and acquire this understanding in the right way. Toon, A. Nonetheless, Zagzebski thinks that believing this actually allows us more understanding for most purposes than the vastly more complicated truth owing to our cognitive limitations. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 2005. For example, in Whitcomb (2011) we find the suggestion that theoretical wisdom is a form of particularly deep understanding. Both are veritic types of luck on Pritchards viewthey are present when, given how one came to have ones true belief, it is a matter of luck that this belief is true (Pritchard 2005: 146). Many seem to blend manipulationism with explanations, suggesting for example that what is required for understanding is an ability associated with mentally manipulating explanations. That is, there is something defective about a scientists would-be understanding of gas behavior were that scientist, unlike all other competent scientists, to reject that the ideal gas law is an idealization and instead embraced it as a fact. It is the idea that one has shifted, or changed, the way he or she takes in knowledge (Rayner, 2011).The fact that taking in knowledge has altered is evident in learning institutions today. However, such a strong view would also make understanding nearly unobtainable and surely very rarefor example, on the extremely strong proposal under consideration, recognized experts in a field would be denied understanding if they had a single false belief about some very minor aspect of the subject matter. Examples of the sort considered suggest thateven if understanding has some important internalist component to ittransparency of the sort Zagzebski is suggesting when putting forward the KU claim, is an accidental property of only some cases of understanding and not essential to understanding. However, advocates of moderate approaches to the factivity of understanding are left with some difficult questions to answer. On the basis of considerations Pritchard argues for in various places (2010; 2012; 2013; 2014), relating to cognitive achievements presence in the absence of knowledge (for example. DePaul, M. Ugly Analysis and Value in A. Haddock, A. Millar and D. Pritchard (eds. One helpful way to think about this is as follows: if one takes a paradigmatic case of an individual who understands a subject matter thoroughly, and manipulates the credence the agent has toward the propositions constituting the subject matter, how low can one go before the agent no longer understands the subject matter in question? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. and Pritchard, D. Varieties of Externalism. Philosophical Issues 41(1) (2014): 63-109. More specifically, Kvanvig aims to support the contention that objectual understanding has a special value knowledge lacks by arguing that the nature of curiositythe motivational element that drives cognitive machinery (2013: 152)underwrites a way of vindicating understandings final value. Grimm (2014) also notes that his modal view of understanding fits well with the idea that understanding involves a kind of ability or know-how, as one who sees or grasps how certain propositions are modally related has the ability to answer a wide variety of questions about how things could have been different. To defend the claim that possessing the kinds of abilities Hills draws attention to is not a matter of simply having extra items of knowledgeshe notes that one could have the extra items of knowledge and still lack the good judgment that allows you to form new, related true beliefs. This is the idea that one has shifted, or changed, the way he or she takes in knowledge. The context-sensitive element of Wilkenfelds account of understanding allows him to attribute adequate understanding to, for example, a student in an introductory history class and yet deny understanding to that student when the context shifts to place him in a room with a panel of experts. Sliwa, P. IVUnderstanding and Knowing. Another significant paper endorsing the claim that knowledge of explanations should play a vital role in our theories of understanding. Summary This chapter contains sections titled: Abstract Introduction Arguments Con Arguments Pro Ambivalence Concerning Relativism? ), The Stanford Enclopedia of Philosophy. (2007: 37-8). Philosophy of Science, 79(1) (2012): 15-37. Kelp (2015) makes a helpful distinction between two broad camps here. Know How. Although a range of epistemologists highlighting some of the important features of understanding-why and objectual understanding have been discussed, there are many interesting topics that warrant further research. Kepler improved on Copernicus by contending that the Earths orbit is not circular, but elliptical. Strevens (2013) focuses on scientific understanding in his discussion of grasping. An important observation Grimm makes is that merely assenting to necessary truths is insufficient for knowing necessary truths a priorione must also grasp orsee the necessity of the necessary truth. However, Elgin takes this line further and insists thatwith some qualificationsfalse central beliefs, and not merely false peripheral beliefs, are compatible with understanding a subject matter to some degree. On the other hand, there are explanationists, who argue that it is knowledge or evaluation of explanations that is doing the relevant work. He also suggests, like Khalifa, that grasping be linked with correct explanations. This is the idea that one has shifted, or changed, the way he or she takes in knowledge. Furthermore, Section 3 considers whether characterizations of understanding that focus on explanation provide a better alternative to views that capitalize on the idea of manipulating representations, also giving due consideration to views that appear to stand outside this divide. In this sense, the history of thought can be seen as the sometimes imperceptibly fluid, sometimes bizarre and abrupt, movements of our concepts. Here is one potential example to illustrate this point: consider that it is not clear that people who desire to understand chemistry generally care about the cause of chemistry. Consider here an analogy: a false belief can be subjectively indistinguishable from knowledge. In short, then, Kvanvig wants to insist that the true beliefs that one attains in acquiring ones understanding can all be Gettiered, even though the Gettier-style luck which prevents these beliefs from qualifying as knowledge does not undermine the understanding this individual acquires. Epistemology is often defined as the theory of knowledge, and talk of propositional knowledge (that is, "S knows that p") has dominated the bulk of modern literature in epistemology. in barn faade cases, where environmental luck is incompatible with knowledge but compatible with cognitive achievement) and the absence of cognitive achievement in the presence of knowledge (e.g. He argues that intuitions that rule against lucky understanding can be explained away. He claims further that this description of the case undermines the intuition that the writers lack of understanding entails the readers lack of understanding. Secondly, one might wonder if Wilkenfelds account of understanding as representation manipulation is too inclusivethat it rules in, as cases of bona fide understanding, representations that are based on inaccurate but internally consistent beliefs. New York: Free Press, 1965. Put generally, according to the coherentist family of proposals of the structure of justified belief, a belief or set of beliefs is justified, or justifiably held, just in case the belief coheres with a set of beliefs, the set forms a coherent system, or some variation on these themes (Olsson 2012: 1). Claims that understanding is entirely compatible with both intervening and environmental forms of veritic luck. There are three potential worries with this general style of approach. For one thing, abstract objects, such as mathematical truths and other atemporal phenomena, can plausibly be understood even though our understanding of them does not seem to require an appreciation of their coming to existence. View Shift in Epistemology.edited.docx from SOCIOLOGY 1010 at Columbia Southern University. facebook android official. A. and Pritchard, D. Knowledge-How and Epistemic Luck. Nos (2013). Kim, J. Hills (2009) is an advocate of such a view of understanding-why in particular. Goldman, A. Dordrecht: Springer, 2014. But in this version of the case, suppose that, although the book is entirely authoritative, genuine and reliable, it is the only trustworthy book on the Comanche on the shelvesevery book on the shelves nearby, which she easily could have grabbed rather than the genuine authoritative book, was filled with rumors and ungrounded suppositions. See, however, Carter & Gordon (2014) for a recent criticism on the point of identifying understanding with strong cognitive achievement. Essentially, this view traditionally holds that understanding why X is the case is equivalent to knowing why X is the case (which is in turn supposed to be equivalent to knowing that X is the case because of Y). Finally, on the other side of the spectrum from Zagzebski and Kvanvig, and also in opposition with Pritchard, is the view that understandings immunity to epistemic luck is isomorphic to knowledges immunity to epistemic luck. For those who wonder about whether the often-discussed grasping associated with understanding might just amount to the possession of further beliefs (rather than, say, the possession of manipulative abilities), this type of view may seem particularly attractive (and comparatively less mysterious). For example, you read many of your books on screens and e-readers today. He claims that while we would generally expect her to have knowledge of her relevant beliefs, this is not essential for her understanding and as a result it would not matter if these true beliefs had been Gettierised (and were therefore merely accidentally true). Grimm puts the template formulation as follows: A Comanche-style case is one in which we form true beliefs on the basis of trusting some source, and either (a) the source is unreliable, or (b) the source is reliable, but in the current environment one might easily have chosen an unreliable source. After analysing variations of the Comanche case so conceived, Grimm argues that in neither (a)- or (b)-style Comanche cases do knowledge and understanding come apart. For example, and problematically for any account of objectual understanding that relaxes a factivity constraint, people frequently retract previous attributions of understanding. However, Baker (2003) has offered an account on which at least some instances of understanding-why are non-factive. He wants us to suppose that grasping has two componentsone that is a purely psychological (that is, narrow) component and one that is the actual obtaining of the state of affairs that is grasped. That said, for manipulationists who are not already inclined to accept the entailment from all-knowing to omni-understanding, the efficacy against the manipulationist is diffused as the example does not get off the ground. Such discussions, though they can be initially helpful, raise a nest of further questions. Explanatory Knowledge and Metaphysical Dependence. In his Essays in the Metaphysics of Mind. Eds. Attempts to explain away the intuitions suggesting that lucky understanding is incompatible with epistemic luck. With a wide range of subtly different accounts of understanding (both objectual and understanding-why) on the table, it will be helpful to consider how understanding interfaces with certain key debates in epistemology. Elgin (2007), like Zagzebski, is sympathetic to a weak factivity constraint on objectual understanding, where the object of understanding is construed as a fairly comprehensive, coherent body of information (2007: 35). In the study of epistemology, philosophers are concerned with the epistemological shift. Includes further discussion of the role of acceptance and belief in her view of understanding. For one thing, if understanding is both a factive and strongly internalist notion then a radical skeptical argument that threatens to show that we have no understanding is a very intimidating prospect (as Pritchard 2010:86 points out). Khalifas indispensability argumentwhich he calls the Grasping Argument runs as follows: Khalifa is, in this argument stipulating that (1) is a ground rule for discussion (2013b: 5). Moral Understanding and Knowledge. Philosophical Studies 172(2) (2015): 113-128. ), The Routledge Companion to Epistemology. In such a parallel case, we simply modify Lackeys original case and suppose that Stella, a creationist teacher, who does not believe in evolution, nonetheless teaches it reliably and in accordance with the highest professional standards. Firstly, Kvanvig introduces propositional understanding as what is attributed in sentences that take the form I understand that X (for example, John understands that he needs to meet Harold at 2pm). Zagzebskis weak approach to a factivity constraint aligns with her broadly internalist thinking about what understanding actually does involvenamely, on her view, internal consistency and what she calls transparency. A theoretical advantage to a weak factivity constraint is that it neatly separates propositional knowledge and objectual understanding as interestingly different. Toon (2015) has recently suggested, with reference to the hypothesis of extended cognition, that understanding can be located partly outside the head. Men He leaves grasping at the level of metaphor or uses it them literally but never develops it. Must they be known or can they be Gettiered true beliefs? Our culture is shifting, Dede argues, not just from valuing the opinions of experts to the participatory culture of YouTube or Facebook, but from understanding knowledge as fixed and linear to a . For Proposes a framework for reducing objectual understanding to what he calls explanatory understanding. Though in light of this fact, it is not obvious that understanding is the appropriate term for this state. Her key thought here is that grasping the truth can actually impede the chances of ones attaining understanding because such a grasp might come at too high a cognitive cost. One point that could potentially invite criticism is the move from (1) and (2) to (3). For one thing, she admits that these abilities can be possessed by degrees. When considering interesting features that might set understanding apart from propositional knowledge, the idea of grasping something is often mentioned. In particular, how we might define expertise and who has it. What kind of historical enterprise is historical epistemology? If making reasonable sense merely requires that some event or experience make sense to the epistemic agent herself, Bakers view appears open, as Grimm (2011) has suggested, to counterexamples according to which an agent knows that something happened and yet accounts for that occurrence by way of a poorly supported theory.
Nfl 2021 2022 Roster Quiz,
King Of The Hammers 2022 Dates,
Illinois Foster Care Payment Rates 2021,
Nikita Dragun Before Surgery,
Articles E